Introduction
On Sept 28, 2019, the World Socialist Web Site reprinted a 1998 lecture by
David North with the title ‘Why are trade
unions hostile to socialism?’ We can
only speculate why North chose to reprint this lecture at this time.
It is notable in that it is practically alone
among North’s numerous writings and lectures, where he ventures to use
“dialectics” to make an argument for a perspective he was defending.
Far more common in North’s oeuvre are
expressions of contempt for dialectics. For some examples of the latter see the
essay
‘Hatred
of the Dialectic’.
North has for decades trumpeted
his role in exposing Gerry Healy’s butchery of dialectics. As we have shown
however, North’s critique of Healy was highly superficial and never got to the
philosophical essence of the matter. (See our introduction to and reprint of
David Bruce’s
‘A
Charlatan Exposed’) The main lesson North drew from his encounter with
Healy is that “dialectics” is a suspicious endeavor and one should avoid it
like the plague. It is therefore notable that in this 1998 lecture North appeals to the
“dialectic” to make his case.
The
results are not much different than those achieved by Healy. A total mess is
made of a half-baked venture into philosophy in order to argue for a position
that is completely untenable.
Dialectics,
which is revolutionary in its essence, is transformed into its opposite, a form
of apologetics for a turn away from the working class.
It just so happens that we are
very familiar with this 1998 lecture because we commented on it in great detail
in Chapter 5 of our book long polemic from 2007,
Marxism
Without its Head of its Heart. We are reprinting our comments on North’s
1998 essay exactly as they appeared in our 2007 polemic.
This is an excerpt from a much longer
piece,
Chapter 5 of
Marxism Without its Head or its Heart.
That chapter is a general critique of the attitude of North’s
organization, the Socialist Equality Party, toward the trade unions.
In reading this discussion it should kept in
mind that it was written 12 years ago and things have moved on since then.
While I think that pointing to the abstentionism of the SEP at that time was
justified, the further degeneration of North’s group since then has transformed
it into an organization openly hostile to the working class.
This was announced loud and clear in their
defense of the Supreme Court’s Janus decision in 2018. (See our essay,
An
anti-working class organization.)
In the following excerpt we have
re-numbered the notes. References following quotes of North’s 1998 lecture
refer to the page number of the printed version of the pamphlet.
******************************************************************************
Rationalizing Abstentionism
The turning away
from an engagement in the struggles of the working class can already be
discerned in North’s lecture, Marxism and the Trade Unions, which was delivered
in January 1998, four and a half years after the Workers League perspectives
resolution. The lecture was intended as a reiteration of the party’s analysis
of the unions, while at the same time contrasting that analysis with the
kowtowing to the bureaucracy of various middle class radical tendencies. But on
a careful reading it becomes evident that there is a shift of emphasis in the
lecture. Whereas the 1993 analysis had been animated by a call for ambitious
new interventions by the party in the working class, there is only a passing
mention of that in the lecture.
Instead a line
of argument is introduced which claims that the “social form” of trade unionism
makes it organically reactionary: “The organic development of trade unionism
proceeds, not in the direction of socialism, but in opposition to it” (11).
This claim is made on supposedly philosophical grounds, and to the extent that
the history of the unions is brought in, it is to confirm the philosophical
argument. At the same time that trade unionism is being depicted as organically
reactionary, there is virtually no mention of the need for the party to involve
itself in new forms of struggle in the working class. What this adds up to, as
we will see, is a rationalization for abstentionism.
The
philosophical argument concerns the relationship of form and content. Here are
the relevant paragraphs:
It
must be kept in mind that when we set out to study trade unionism, we are
dealing with a definite social form. By this, we mean not some sort of casual,
accidental and amorphous collection of individuals, but rather a
historically-evolved connection between people organized in classes and rooted
in certain specific relations of production. It is also important to reflect
upon the nature of form itself. We all know that a relation exists between form
and content, but this relationship is generally conceived as if the form were
merely the expression of content. From this standpoint, the social form might
be conceptualized as merely an outward, plastic and infinitely malleable
expression of the relations upon which it is based. But social forms are more
profoundly understood as dynamic elements in the historical process. To say
that "content is formed" means that form imparts to the content of
which it is the expression definite qualities and characteristics. It is
through form that content exists and develops.
Perhaps
it will be possible to clarify the purpose of this detour into the realm of
philosophical categories and abstractions, by referring to the famous section
in the first chapter of the first volume of Capital, in which Marx asks:
"Whence, then, arises the enigmatical character of the product of labor,
so soon as it assumes the form of commodities? Clearly from the form
itself." That is, when a product of labor assumes the form of a commodity
a transformation that occurs only at a certain stage of society it acquires a
peculiar, fetishistic quality that it did not previously possess. Once products
are exchanged on the market, real social relations between people, of which
commodities are themselves the outcome, necessarily assume the appearance of a
relation between things. A product of labor is a product of labor; and yet,
once it assumes, within the framework of new productive relations, the form of
a commodity, it acquires new and extraordinary social properties.
Similarly,
a group of workers is a group of workers. And yet, when that group assumes the
form of a trade union, it acquires, through that form, new and quite distinct
social properties to which the workers are inevitably subordinated. What,
precisely, is meant by this? The trade unions represent the working class in a
very distinct socio-economic role: as the seller of a commodity, labor power.
Arising on the basis of the productive relations and property forms of
capitalism, the essential purpose of the trade union is to secure for this
commodity the best price that can be obtained under prevailing market
conditions (12-13).
Now, we are the last people who would object to bringing in philosophy
into such a discussion, especially since it is such a rare occurrence in the
party’s lectures or articles. But in this case the resort to ‘dialectics’ turns
out to be spurious. First, the relationship of form to content is conceived of
in a static and one-sided way. North views the form (i.e. the union) as the
active agent, while the content (the working class) is the passive recipient.
But as any student of dialectics should know, what is passive at one moment in
relation to its active opposite plays the opposite role at the next moment. It
is not only form that determines content but content that can also determine
form (or, as Hegel puts it nicely, “‘content’ is
nothing but the overturning of form into content, and ‘form’ nothing but the
overturning of content into form”[1]). What this means in relation to the unions
is that the content of the class struggle, although hamstrung by the
limitations imposed on it by what we can call here the ‘union-form’, threatens
to overreach the limits of that form. At that point, the possibility exists of
the newly emerging content (to paraphrase Marx) breaking up the integument of
the existing form.[2]
Thus what North is presenting here is a static formalism that ignores the
fluidity of the concepts of form and content.
Second, the analogy of a commodity to a union leaves out
something important: workers are not things. A worker is not ‘stamped’ by union
membership to the same extent that a product becomes stamped as a commodity in
a market economy. Though in the form of the union, workers are defined as
sellers of labor-power, the content of that social relation is the class
struggle. It is that content which makes it possible for workers to become
conscious of their exploitation and of their revolutionary role as society’s
chief productive force, thereby empowering them to overthrow the existing
relations of production. To state the obvious, a product of labor cannot become
conscious; it cannot escape its commodity-form so long as capitalism exists.
But workers aren’t imprisoned by the ‘union-form’ to anywhere near the same
extent: the dynamic within unions is much more tenuous, with the class struggle
always lurking as a threat to the ‘normal
business’ of class collaboration. It is this very instability that
accounts for the heavy-handedness of the bureaucracy: they can only maintain
their domination by quashing any manifestation of dissent.
This side of the matter is lost sight of in North’s ruminations
on the trade unions as a social form: for him that form imparts “distinct
social properties to which the workers are inevitably subordinated.” To be
sure, the subordination is real enough, but why is it necessarily inevitable?
It is only so if one leaves out the possibility of workers ever being able to
attain socialist consciousness so long as they are within unions. In other
words, what North is saying here is that purely by virtue of the fact that
workers are union members, it becomes impossible for the revolutionary movement
to win them over. The historical account of the unions that North offers up is
meant to make such a case, but as we’ll soon see, it is a highly selective
reading of that history. But before we get to that, we can already anticipate
serious problems in North’s position. Seeing as (according to Lenin) trade
unionism is the highest level that the spontaneous consciousness of the working
class can reach within bourgeois society, it would seem that if North is right,
then any breakthrough to socialist consciousness by the working class becomes
virtually impossible. The workers will go on spontaneously reproducing the
trade union-form, and that form will then “inevitably” subordinate them to
capitalism, irrespective of what the revolutionary party does to reach them.
This is a dead-end theoretically, and politically it amounts to giving up on
the struggle for class consciousness with a shrug of resignation.
So it is no coincidence that the ambitious proposals for
intervening in the working class that had been envisioned in 1993 are forgotten
about in this lecture. Back then the perspectives resolution declared: “The
party must strive to create new forms of struggle among these workers [i.e.
those already in unions], including factory committees and even trade unions,
organized independently and in opposition to the AFL-CIO.” Even trade unions!
But in light of North’s lecture, this proposal no longer made any sense: it
would hardly matter if these unions were independently organized and opposed to
the bureaucracy because the union-form itself would make them organically
reactionary.
And why limit this just to unions? Why
can’t the same ‘formal’ principle apply to factory committees or neighborhood
committees to fight evictions and school closures or indeed any formation of
the working class that arises spontaneously within capitalism? Precisely
because of their spontaneous character, such formations will start out by
accepting the limits of capitalism and seek to bargain for better conditions
within the system: for example, a factory committee will seek to be a militant
and honest alternative to the official union or else (in a non-union plant) try
to establish itself as a union. And to the extent that these committees remain
bound by spontaneity – i.e. to the extent that they remain cut off from a
revolutionary socialist perspective – then it is certainly true that their
‘organic’ development will ultimately be in a reactionary direction. But one
might as well say the same thing about spontaneous consciousness as such: it is
bourgeois consciousness, as Lenin informed us long ago. But this is hardly the
end of the matter as far as Marxists are concerned: formations like factory
committees are also battlegrounds in the struggle for class consciousness.
But this is what North’s ‘formalism’ deliberately obscures.
The analysis of
the unions in the 1993 resolution had been much closer to a genuinely
dialectical conception. It was not form abstracted from content but huge shifts
in the world economy brought about by globalization that had pushed the
traditional unions past the point of no return. It was in this sense that the
resolution had argued against the “superficial tendency” of the petty bourgeois
radicals to ascribe the problems of the unions to bad or treacherous leaders:
the deeper dimensions of the problem were about how class collaboration
and nationalist orientations were no longer viable within a globalized
capitalism.
But North’s
lecture moves in a different direction: by rooting the problem of the unions in
their form, he produces another kind of “organizational fetishism”, one which
doesn’t transcend the radicals’ position so much as invert its terms. In effect
the argument now is that the unions were a hopeless cause from the start, and
by implication the same would be true of any union-like formation, which is to
say any spontaneous formation of the working class. So while the organizational
fetishism of the radicals leads to opportunism, North’s fetishism-in-reverse
leads to abstentionism. But the second is as much an abandonment of
revolutionary practice as the first.
What the History of the Unions
Really Shows
To be sure, the
degeneration of the unions was not some sudden demise of otherwise healthy
organizations. It was a protracted process, and to the extent that they have
been free of revolutionary ‘disruptions’, the unions have veered towards
corporatism. Their bureaucratic encrustation, the suppression of internal
democracy and the all but total exclusion of socialists have rendered the
traditional unions largely impervious to any countervailing progressive
tendencies. One might add here, however, that even in regard to this
reactionary tendency of the unions, North’s ‘formalist’ argument sheds very
little light. We can learn far more from Lenin in What is to be done?:
there he notes the spontaneous movement of the working class (which includes
the trade unions) moves “along the line of least resistance”, and for that
reason it tends to move in a reactionary direction so long as it is unimpeded
by revolutionary consciousness. This is because within bourgeois society it is
bourgeois ideology that prevails, and so the line of least resistance is always
the line that accommodates itself to capitalism.[3]
This insight gets us out of North’s prison-house of the ‘union-form’ and into
the dialectic of the class struggle: the line of least resistance is indeed a
powerful tendency but by no means an omnipotent one to which workers must be
“inevitably subordinated.”
In any case, the
history of the unions is not just one long, uninterrupted record of degeneration
(or of the union-form manifesting its organically reactionary nature, as North
would have it). There have also been important episodes in which the class
struggle broke through the integument of bourgeois trade unionism, episodes in
which revolutionary consciousness gained the upper hand over spontaneity. To be
sure, these episodes have been relatively brief, with the line of least
resistance eventually reasserting itself. But one could say much the same about
the socialist revolution: it has had few breakthroughs, a great many more
betrayals and defeats, and eventually even the breakthroughs have been
reversed. On the basis of such a record one could use North’s logic to argue
that there was something ‘organically’ flawed about the ‘form’ of the socialist
revolution – that while it may not be reactionary, it most certainly is
unrealistic. And this is of course a widely held position, but presumably not
among revolutionary Marxists.
To make his
case, however, North has to downplay or ignore any revolutionary ‘intrusions’
into union history. He focuses on the labor movements in England and Germany
prior to World War One, which he claims provide “the greatest historical test
of trade unionism” (30). This is because, though the two labor movements developed
in different ways, they ended up in the same, reactionary, place: the German
unions, established by the Social Democrats, played no less a
counterrevolutionary role than the English unions, which had emerged
independently of the socialist movement. And it is certainly true that, as
differing paradigms of the development of trade unionism, the English and
German examples are significant. But North freights these examples with a much
greater burden than they can sustain: he makes them out to be the decisive
“test” of trade unionism, a test that had already been passed and failed by
1914!
But the
(relatively brief) account that North’s lecture provides of the history of
these labor movements doesn’t come close to proving his case. What it does do
is confirm something every literate Marxist already knows – which is that trade
union consciousness is bourgeois consciousness. Take the German case, which is
the more telling of the two because, as North notes, “the trade unions emerged
under the direct tutelage of the socialist movement. Its leaders were
diligently schooled in the teachings of Marx and Engels. And yet, in essence,
the German trade unions were no more devoted to socialism than those in
England” (25). And North goes on to show that the larger the unions grew, the
more the union leaders bridled under the control of the SPD, and when it came
to the party’s revolutionary wing under Rosa Luxemburg, the animosity of the
union leaders “assumed pathological dimensions” (27). By 1906, under pressure
from the unions, the SPD adopted the principle of equality between the unions
and the party, which meant that from then on “the SPD was effectively ruled by
the general commission of the trade unions” (28), and this in turn accelerated
the party’s right wing trajectory that ultimately led it to the historic
betrayal of August 1914.
North sees these
facts as confirming his argument: if union leaders “diligently schooled in the
teachings of Marx and Engels” can still betray, then surely the fault lies in
the ‘union-form’ itself. But we can far more adequately account for this
history by going back to one of the key thoughts of What is to be done?
– trade union consciousness is bourgeois consciousness. For Lenin, needless to
say, this was anything but a rationalization for abstentionism; instead, it
meant that Marxists had to wage a persistent struggle within the unions against
the spontaneous pull of bourgeois ideology: “[T]he
task of Social-Democracy is to combat spontaneity, to divert
the working-class movement from this spontaneous, trade-unionist striving to
come under the wing of the bourgeoisie, and to bring it under the wing of
revolutionary Social Democracy.”[4]
When
we consider the history of the German unions in that light, then something
important becomes evident that North’s formalism obscures: the real culprit
in this history is not the unions but the SPD. North makes it seem as if
the unions, because of their organically reactionary form, corrupted the SPD
and dragged it to its demise, but this is a superficial reading of what
happened. The unions were bound to end up “under the wing of the
bourgeoisie” so long as there was no consistent effort by the SPD “to combat
spontaneity.” But “combat” on this front, as on many others, is not something
the SPD did much of; on the contrary, at every critical juncture the party
capitulated to the pressure of the unions, choosing ‘unity’ over principle.
Thus, what seems like a case of the unions dragging the party down is really
much more a story about how the party abandoned its revolutionary
responsibilities to resist that pressure and “divert” the union
membership to socialist consciousness. In other words, it was not the ‘form’ of
the unions but the opportunism of the SPD that was the decisive factor.
As for the
‘diligent schooling’ the SPD offered its union leaders, this did nothing to
resist the pull of spontaneous consciousness. The SPD leaders treated Marxism
like a catechism: attending an occasional lecture or party school in no way
impinged on ‘the real business’ of running the unions, anymore than did the
perennial speeches by party leaders about ‘the inevitable victory of
socialism’. It was Bernstein’s motto – ‘the movement is everything, the goal is
nothing’ – that not only expressed his own reformism but also accurately
described the reality within the SPD, despite the angry objections of the
orthodox party leaders.[5]
This is why the German unions are not the decisive test of the union-form that
North makes them out to be. “No bridge existed,” as Trotsky says in The
Transitional Program, between the minimum and maximum programs of the SPD,[6]
i.e. between the nickel-and-diming of bourgeois unionism on the one hand and
the socialist revolution on the other. When measured by that standard – i.e. by
the extent to which revolutionaries fought to a build a bridge to socialist
consciousness, by the extent to which they resisted bourgeois consciousness within
the unions – what ultimately stands out about the German experience is more its
similarities to the English experience than its differences.
To bolster his
case, North stitches together quotes from Marx and Engels, Luxemburg, Trotsky
and Gramsci to demonstrate that they were frequently critical of the unions,
especially of the hostility of the labor bureaucracy to the class struggle and
socialism. And it is certainly true that the great classical Marxists were
often scathing about the union bureaucracy and they certainly never fetishized
the unions in the way that some petty bourgeois radicals do today. Trotsky put
it nicely in The Transitional Program: “Trade unions are not ends in
themselves; they are but means along the road to proletarian revolution.”[7]
But this is still a long way from justifying North’s position, which is that the
unions aren’t even a means. In any case, all the Marxists that North
cites could also be quoted as being adamantly opposed to abstentionism with
regard to the unions. Their fundamental concern was that revolutionaries had to
intervene in the mass movement of the working class.
A relevant
example here is Trotsky’s attitude to the German unions in the early Thirties
in the course of the struggle against the rising threat of Nazism. These are
the same unions that, according to North, had already been ‘tested’ by 1914 and
found to be organically reactionary, but that certainly wasn’t how Trotsky
approached them. When the Stalinists (in line with their ‘ultra-left’ Third
Period) denounced the reformist unions as ‘social fascist’ and abandoned them
to set up their own ‘revolutionary unions’, Trotsky condemned this
dual-unionism: he argued that all it achieved was to isolate the
revolutionaries from the great bulk of the working class, who remained in the
traditional unions. Trotsky considered “the restoration of the unity of the
trade unions” crucial to the success of the German revolution because this
would create optimal conditions for exposing the impotence of the reformists in
fighting fascism, thereby winning over the ranks to a revolutionary
perspective. Indeed, he insisted that “it is precisely within the trade unions
that an exceptionally fruitful field is now open for action.”[8]
And that
epitomizes the attitude of all the leading classical Marxists – that the unions
were a potentially “fruitful field” for revolutionaries. Certainly from Lenin’s
time on, that view of the unions came without illusions that trade unionism was
anything more than bourgeois consciousness. The ‘fruit’, so to speak, wasn’t
simply there for the picking; it could only be had through a determined
struggle for socialist consciousness. For most of the 20th century,
that orientation to the unions was an essentially correct one. What has
necessitated a change was the onset of globalization, which rendered the
traditional unions largely moribund. But this posed the need for new forms of
struggle by the working class, including new unions. North’s position has led
instead to abstentionism, which is to say, to an estrangement of the
revolutionary movement from the working class. And that position is plainly
irreconcilable with the tradition of classical Marxism, notwithstanding the
selective account of that tradition that North presents.
A Case Ignored: the Russian Unions
A real test of
North’s theory would have required a case where Marxists conducted a genuine
struggle against “the spontaneous, trade unionist striving to come under the
wing of the bourgeoisie” but were unable to overcome that tendency. And history
provides at least one instance where the Marxist movement was able to conduct
such a struggle on a mass scale – in Russia. It is significant that North
doesn’t talk about Russia in his lecture. He does briefly mention it in a
polemic against the Spartacists, Globalization and the International Working
Class: A Marxist Assessment, [9]
which was written the same year (1998) as the lecture, but his remarks are
anything but illuminating. He writes: “It is worth noting that the Russian
unions played no appreciable role in the October Revolution. Indeed, the large
rail workers union, which was dominated by the Mensheviks, worked actively
against the socialist overthrow.”[10]
This is
nonsense. While it is true that there were unions under Menshevik control that
opposed the revolution, there were a good many more that sided with the
Bolsheviks. (Moreover, as John Reed noted in Ten Days That Shook the World, the
only reason the rail workers union came out against the revolution was because
the union executive deliberately postponed internal elections, knowing that
they would be swept out of office by the Bolsheviks.[11])
North is simply trying to evade an important piece of history that doesn’t fit
with his theory about the organically reactionary nature of the union form. To
be sure, the role the unions played in the revolution was a supporting rather
than a leading one, but that is all that any Marxist would ever have expected.
The unions could never be a substitute for the party, but to the extent that
they provided a working class base for Bolshevism, their role in the revolution
was indeed an appreciable one. With his eye for the telling detail, John Reed
gives us a memorable glimpse at what unions meant to wide layers of the working
class just awakening to political consciousness in the course of the
revolution:
…Russia
was in travail, bearing a new world. The servants one used to treat like
animals and pay next to nothing, were getting independent. A pair of shoes cost
more than a hundred rubles, and as wages averaged about thirty-five rubles a
month the servants refused to stand in queue and wear out their shoes.
But more than that. In the new Russia every man and woman could vote; there
were working-class newspapers, saying new and startling things; there were the
Soviets; and there were the Unions. The izvoshtchiki (cab-drivers) had
a Union; they were also represented in the Petrograd Soviet. The waiters and
hotel servants were organized, and refused tips. On the walls of restaurants
they put up signs which read, “No tips taken here–” or, “Just because a man has
to make his living waiting on table is no reason to insult him by offering him
a tip!”[12]
Of course the
great ferment of the revolution produced new forms of struggle, most famously
soviets as well as factory committees, and the activities of these various
formations often overlapped. But the unions were by no means the least
important or the most conservative of these formations. Indeed, when it came to
the critical moment of the insurrection, it was the soviets that proved to be
more of an obstacle than the unions! In The History of the Russian
Revolution, Trotsky writes about the “fetishism of organizational forms” –
meaning here the soviets – on the part of conservative elements within the
party (notably Kamenev and Zinoviev) opposed to the seizure of power[13]:
they used the fact that the soviets were still formally under the control of
the reformist parties to argue that the insurrection had to be put off
indefinitely. For Lenin and Trotsky, the soviets were never (as Trotsky put it
elsewhere) “a panacea”,[14]
and if the obstructionism of the reformists couldn’t be overcome within the
soviets, then the alternative was to turn to the factory committees and the
unions as the direct organs of workers’ power:
The
question, what mass organizations were to serve the party for leadership in the
insurrection, did not permit an a priori, much less a categorical, answer.
The instruments of the insurrection might have been the factory committees and
trade unions, already under the leadership of the Bolsheviks, and at the same
time in individual cases certain soviets that had broken free from the yoke of
the Compromisers. Lenin, for example, said to Ordzhonikidze: “We must swing
over the center of gravity to the factory and shop committees. The factory and
shop committees must become the organs of insurrection.”[15]
Thus the test of the Russian experience plays
havoc with North’s theory. If it were possible for the Bolsheviks to use the
unions as one of their “instruments of the insurrection,” then clearly the
union-form is not organically impervious to the revolutionary content of the
class struggle. In other words, the class interests of workers are not
“inevitably subordinated” to capitalism purely by virtue of this form. It all
depends on the extent to which revolutionaries can overcome the prevailing
“line of least resistance.”
In this respect, unions are no different than any
other spontaneous formation of the working class, including even soviets. There
isn’t an organizational form in the working class more closely associated with
the socialist revolution than soviets, and yet in 1918-19, the SDP used the
workers’ councils in Germany (Trotsky called them the “Ebert-Scheidemann
soviets”) to strangle the revolution, and the SDP’s Russian counterparts in
1917 would have done the same, had it not been for the opposition of the
Bolsheviks. Moreover, under Stalin the Russian soviets were gutted of any
revolutionary content and incorporated into the apparatus of the bureaucratic
dictatorship. But it would be perverse on this basis to argue that the soviets
as a social form are organically reactionary. As Trotsky remarked in relation
to the point he made about the soviets not being a panacea: “The soviets are
only an organizational form; the question is decided by the class content of
the policy and by no means by its form.”[16] And
that is also true of the unions: it is not their form but “the class content of
their policy” which has determined their evolution.
The Russian soviets have long since gone to the
dustbin of history and the traditional unions are now joining them there. The
task of revolutionaries is to intervene in the mass struggles of the working
class, to help develop new forms of struggle – whether that be new unions,
factory and strike committees and eventually new soviets as well – and to fight
to fill those forms with revolutionary content. This is the only standpoint
consistent with classical Marxism, but it is a standpoint that the
International Committee, under North’s tutelage, has abandoned.
[1] G.W.F.
Hegel, The Encyclopedia Logic,
(Hackett Publishing, 1991), p. 202.
[2] “The
monopoly of capital becomes a fetter on the mode of production which has
flourished alongside and under it. The centralization of the means of
production and the socialization of labour reach a point at which they become
incompatible with their capitalist integument.
This integument is burst asunder.
The knell of capitalist private property sounds. The expropriators are
expropriated.” Marx, Capital, Volume I,
(Penguin Classics, 1990), p. 929.
[5] Bernstein’s biographer Peter Gay
recounts how a prominent SPD leader, Ignaz Auer, wrote to Bernstein to
complain, not about the content of his views, but rather about his indiscretion
in making them public. Bernstein had wanted the party to pass a resolution
acknowledging its reformist character, to which Auer responded: “My dear Ede,
you don’t pass such resolutions. You don’t talk about it, you
just do it” (The Dilemma of Democratic Socialism, p. 270). This
private remark says a good deal about the internal life of the SPD.
[6] The
Transitional Program, p. 75.
[9] Though
this polemic was issued in the name of the ICFI, it is evident both from the
style and substance that it was written by North.
[15] The
History of the Russian Revolution, ibid.
[16]
“Thaelmann and the ‘People’s Revolution’”, ibid.